Skip to main content
Social Sci LibreTexts

11.7: Conclusion

  • Page ID
    138686
  • \( \newcommand{\vecs}[1]{\overset { \scriptstyle \rightharpoonup} {\mathbf{#1}} } \) \( \newcommand{\vecd}[1]{\overset{-\!-\!\rightharpoonup}{\vphantom{a}\smash {#1}}} \)\(\newcommand{\id}{\mathrm{id}}\) \( \newcommand{\Span}{\mathrm{span}}\) \( \newcommand{\kernel}{\mathrm{null}\,}\) \( \newcommand{\range}{\mathrm{range}\,}\) \( \newcommand{\RealPart}{\mathrm{Re}}\) \( \newcommand{\ImaginaryPart}{\mathrm{Im}}\) \( \newcommand{\Argument}{\mathrm{Arg}}\) \( \newcommand{\norm}[1]{\| #1 \|}\) \( \newcommand{\inner}[2]{\langle #1, #2 \rangle}\) \( \newcommand{\Span}{\mathrm{span}}\) \(\newcommand{\id}{\mathrm{id}}\) \( \newcommand{\Span}{\mathrm{span}}\) \( \newcommand{\kernel}{\mathrm{null}\,}\) \( \newcommand{\range}{\mathrm{range}\,}\) \( \newcommand{\RealPart}{\mathrm{Re}}\) \( \newcommand{\ImaginaryPart}{\mathrm{Im}}\) \( \newcommand{\Argument}{\mathrm{Arg}}\) \( \newcommand{\norm}[1]{\| #1 \|}\) \( \newcommand{\inner}[2]{\langle #1, #2 \rangle}\) \( \newcommand{\Span}{\mathrm{span}}\)\(\newcommand{\AA}{\unicode[.8,0]{x212B}}\)

    In this chapter we have looked at several types of expressions in various languages that seem to contribute “use-conditional” rather than truth-conditional meanings. The characteristic properties of such expressions are those identified by Potts in his work on conventional implicatures. They tend to be speakeroriented; independent of and secondary to the at-issue, truth-conditional content of the utterance; excluded from negation and questioning; and not assumed to be part of common ground.

    We noted that speech act adverbials in English (e.g. frankly, confidentially) can function either as sentence adverbs with use-conditional meanings, or as manner adverbs with truth-conditional meanings. In future chapters we will see that similar ambiguities arise with certain conjunctions, notably because (Chapter 18) and if (Chapter 19). We will argue that, at least for because, such ambiguities need not be treated as polysemy (distinct senses), but can be seen as a kind of pragmatic ambiguity: a single sense that can function on two levels, modifying the sentence meaning or the utterance meaning. In the first case, it contributes truth-conditional meaning, while in the second case it contributes use-conditional meaning.

    Further reading

    Potts (2007a,b) and (2012) provide concise introductions to his analysis of conventional implicatures. Potts (2007c) focuses more specifically on expressives. Scheffler (2013) applies this analysis to sentence adverbs in English and German. Gutzmann (2015) presents an introduction to the idea of use-conditional meaning in chapter 2, and an analysis of the German “modal particles” in chapter 7.

    Discussion exercises

    A. Use the kinds of evidence discussed in this chapter to determine whether the italicized expressions in the following examples contribute truth-conditional or use-conditional meaning:

    1. Sir Richard Whittington, a medieval cloth merchant, served four terms as Lord Mayor of London.
    2. Wilma probably loves sauerkraut.
    3. Fred loves sauerkraut too.
    4. Mrs. Natasha Griggs, who served six years as MP for Darwin, is a cancer survivor.
    5. Baxter reportedly supported Suharto.

    This page titled 11.7: Conclusion is shared under a CC BY 4.0 license and was authored, remixed, and/or curated by Paul Kroeger (Language Library Press) via source content that was edited to the style and standards of the LibreTexts platform; a detailed edit history is available upon request.

    • Was this article helpful?