Skip to main content
Social Sci LibreTexts

15.4: Structural Ambiguity

  • Page ID
    192757
    • Catherine Anderson, Bronwyn Bjorkman, Derek Denis, Julianne Doner, Margaret Grant, Nathan Sanders, and Ai Taniguchi
    • eCampusOntario

    \( \newcommand{\vecs}[1]{\overset { \scriptstyle \rightharpoonup} {\mathbf{#1}} } \)

    \( \newcommand{\vecd}[1]{\overset{-\!-\!\rightharpoonup}{\vphantom{a}\smash {#1}}} \)

    \( \newcommand{\id}{\mathrm{id}}\) \( \newcommand{\Span}{\mathrm{span}}\)

    ( \newcommand{\kernel}{\mathrm{null}\,}\) \( \newcommand{\range}{\mathrm{range}\,}\)

    \( \newcommand{\RealPart}{\mathrm{Re}}\) \( \newcommand{\ImaginaryPart}{\mathrm{Im}}\)

    \( \newcommand{\Argument}{\mathrm{Arg}}\) \( \newcommand{\norm}[1]{\| #1 \|}\)

    \( \newcommand{\inner}[2]{\langle #1, #2 \rangle}\)

    \( \newcommand{\Span}{\mathrm{span}}\)

    \( \newcommand{\id}{\mathrm{id}}\)

    \( \newcommand{\Span}{\mathrm{span}}\)

    \( \newcommand{\kernel}{\mathrm{null}\,}\)

    \( \newcommand{\range}{\mathrm{range}\,}\)

    \( \newcommand{\RealPart}{\mathrm{Re}}\)

    \( \newcommand{\ImaginaryPart}{\mathrm{Im}}\)

    \( \newcommand{\Argument}{\mathrm{Arg}}\)

    \( \newcommand{\norm}[1]{\| #1 \|}\)

    \( \newcommand{\inner}[2]{\langle #1, #2 \rangle}\)

    \( \newcommand{\Span}{\mathrm{span}}\) \( \newcommand{\AA}{\unicode[.8,0]{x212B}}\)

    \( \newcommand{\vectorA}[1]{\vec{#1}}      % arrow\)

    \( \newcommand{\vectorAt}[1]{\vec{\text{#1}}}      % arrow\)

    \( \newcommand{\vectorB}[1]{\overset { \scriptstyle \rightharpoonup} {\mathbf{#1}} } \)

    \( \newcommand{\vectorC}[1]{\textbf{#1}} \)

    \( \newcommand{\vectorD}[1]{\overrightarrow{#1}} \)

    \( \newcommand{\vectorDt}[1]{\overrightarrow{\text{#1}}} \)

    \( \newcommand{\vectE}[1]{\overset{-\!-\!\rightharpoonup}{\vphantom{a}\smash{\mathbf {#1}}}} \)

    \( \newcommand{\vecs}[1]{\overset { \scriptstyle \rightharpoonup} {\mathbf{#1}} } \)

    \( \newcommand{\vecd}[1]{\overset{-\!-\!\rightharpoonup}{\vphantom{a}\smash {#1}}} \)

    Note: This is adapted from Section 6.17

    When we talked about morphology, we saw a first example of structural ambiguity in Section 5.9: cases where the same string of morphemes can have more than one structure, with each structure corresponding to a different
    interpretation.

    The same thing is found in syntax. Consider the following example:

    (1)   I saw someone with a telescope.

    This has two possible interpretations:

    1. I was using a telescope, and I saw someone. (PP modifies VP)
    2. I saw someone, and that person had a telescope. (PP modifies NP)

    When a sentence is restated with a new wording, it is called a paraphrase. You may be asked to provide paraphrases of the two meanings of an ambiguous sentence and draw the trees that represent the two meanings an a linguistics assignment or test. If you are asked to do this, make sure your paraphrases aren’t also ambiguous, and make sure you draw a tree of the original sentence, not your paraphrase.

    In the first interpretation, the prepositional phrase [PP with a telescope] modifies the verb phrase headed by saw. In the second interpretation, the same prepositional phrase modifies the noun phrase someone. These two structures are illustrated below:

    [S [NP I] [VP saw [NP someone] [PP with a telescope]]]
    Figure A1.11: Tree diagram showing [PP with a telescope] as a modifier of the verb, meaning “I used a telescope to see someone”.
    [S [NP I] [VP saw [NP someone [PP with a telescope]]]]
    Figure A1.12: Tree diagram showing [PP with a telescope] as a modifier of the NP object, meaning “I saw a person and that person had a telescope”

    The same will be true for other cases of structural ambiguity—each meaning will correspond to a different potential tree structure.

    We can use the principle of modification, repeated in (2), to decide how to draw structurally ambiguous sentences.

    (2) Principle of Modification
      If an XP modifies a head Y, then XP must be Y’s sister, or, in other words, XP must be the daughter of YP

    If we apply this to the sentence in (1), we may notice that with a telescope can modify either the verb saw or the noun someone. If it modifies the verb saw, it will have the meaning that the act of seeing was done using a telescope and the PP will be sister to the verb, as shown in Figure A1.11. On the other hand, if the PP modifies the noun someone, it will have the meaning that the someone has the telescope and the PP will be sister to the noun, as shown in Figure A1.12.

    Query \(\PageIndex{1}\)

    This page titled 15.4: Structural Ambiguity is shared under a CC BY-NC-SA 4.0 license and was authored, remixed, and/or curated by Catherine Anderson, Bronwyn Bjorkman, Derek Denis, Julianne Doner, Margaret Grant, Nathan Sanders, and Ai Taniguchi (eCampusOntario) via source content that was edited to the style and standards of the LibreTexts platform; a detailed edit history is available upon request.